The Development of Something and Other
The Other
Other
is first determined at the end of the
the development of something
and the two now form a pair that progress the logic further. Before looking at
that development, however, a semantic issue needs to be settled: is an other
actually a category in its own right and not merely a reflection of something
?
Both something
and other
are each determined as
existents
as well as
something
in its own right. An other
is just as much a something
in its
own right. Their difference may appear to be merely semantic, such as a sentence
ordering—for example, this bulletin is different from that other
one—such that something
and other
are essentially the same (see
Hegel 2010, 90-91/21.105-106). Hegel, however, claims that there is a logical
difference between the two determinations, and that the other
is a particular
determination in its own right: “other, as posited at first, though an other
with reference to something, is other also for itself apart from the
something” (Hegel 2010, 91/21.106).
Hegel illustrates this in the common usage of nature, particularly as it is regarded as other of human self-conscious activity or spirit. At first, the determinateness of nature expresses a mere relativity—a something different from the matter at hand—but what is implied in this is not that the externality of nature merely exists within self-conscious thought as such, but that externality is a quality of nature itself: “taken for itself the quality of nature is just this, to be the other within, that which-exists-outside-itself” (Hegel 2010, 92/21.106).
Coincidentally, the term nature encompasses its own set of concepts which are
each determined and developed through the primitives of space, time and
matter—categories which are precisely further concrete elaborations on the
theme of that which-exists-outside-itself. It is important to remember,
however, that while nature may exemplify the idea of the other
, the concept of
the other
does not logically depend on nature; one does not need to appeal to
nature in order to conceptualize otherness. Hegel develops this concept of the
other
entirely out of the concept of something
, immanently.
While it is not yet clear why other
is a category distinct from something
, a
couple of clues may act as helpful stepping stones towards that understanding.
First, there is a distinction to be made between a something
that entirely
and immanently develops from pure being
and the something
that is as the
result of an other something
. Second, the distinction between an immediate
something
and a mediated something
holds—or, does not
collapse—because the quality of being something
means to have a
being-within-itself
or an internality, such that the two somethings
cannot
collapse into one. Instead, the two somethings
must form a new difference
vis-á-vis one another. Additionally, this new difference cannot be relational
or a concrete unity, since that would require a third element to bind the other
two, which would be presupposing too much. Rather, the difference must be
contained within each something
, perhaps as the feature of being something
.
The Other of the Other
The other which is such for itself is the other within it, hence the other of itself and so the other of the other – therefore, the absolutely unequal in itself, that which negates itself, alters itself. But it equally remains identical with itself, for that into which it alters is the other, and this other has no additional determination; but that which alters itself is not determined in any other way than in this, to be an other; in going over to this other, it only unites with itself. It is thus posited as reflected into itself with sublation of the otherness, a self-identical something from which the otherness, which is at the same time a moment of it, is therefore distinct, itself not appertaining to it as something (Hegel 2010, 92/21.106).
Not only is the other
a determinateness that applies with regards to
something
, two somethings
(non-quantitatively) or something
and other
,
but it also applies to the other
as such. This yields the peculiar notion that
an other
is an other
to itself. To phrase this using a different term:
externality is external to itself.
This conception of the other of the other
produces two absolutely contrary
determinations. First, by virtue of being _other_
, the inner other
is
completely unequal to the outer other
, and since this determination is
within the other
, it essentially negates itself or, as Hegel puts it, alters
(verändert) itself. Second, by the same token, the inner other
is perfectly
identical to the outer other
since they are both equally other
, such that
the other
thereby rejoins itself as it is. This movement of “othering” servers
to change the other
but what it changes into is nothing else than other
again.
but that which alters itself is not determined in any other way than in this, to
be an other; in going over to this other, it only unites with itself.
The first instinct might be to conclude that no change took place in this
“othering”. But reading Hegel carefully, it is understood that the first
determination of the other of the other
—that the inner and outer other
are unequal—does in fact take place without reference to the second. The
first determination thus is not dependent on the second for its validity, and so
the second does not have the authority to revoke the determination of the first.
Granted that the other
is other
to itself, the second determination
necessarily follows from the first.
The second determination—that the inner and outer other
are
equal—does also in fact run completely counter to the first. It really
does appear that a contradiction follows from the other of the other
; but this
precisely displays the movement of change itself whereby an element of
difference and identity are necessarily both contained. In everyday parlance,
this is readily grasped and accepted: it does not make sense to say a matter has
changed if there is not some unity between its two states, but likewise it does
not make more sense to say that there is no difference, since then there would
be no different states to speak of. Change, it seems, must incorporate these two
elements. What Hegel shows here is how change minimally develops from the
“inside-out”, as it were, by thinking what logically follows from the idea of
other
when the category is turned upon itself.
Being-for-other
The something preserves itself in its non-being; it is essentially one with it, and essentially not one with it. It therefore stands in reference to an otherness without being just this otherness. The otherness is at once contained in it and yet separated from it; it is being-for-other (Hegel 2010, 92/21.106).
Being-for-other
(Sein-für-Anderes) determines the state of something
whereby it is connected to an other
while also not merely being this
other
. One might say it is the “outward facing aspect” of something
. This
“aspect”, however, is internally part of what it means to be something
such
that it is not a determination externally imputed upon a something
. It follows
from the nature of something
that it has a being-for-other
.
Existence as such is an immediate, bare of references; or, it is in the determination of being. However, as including non-being within itself, existence is determinate being, being negated within itself, and then in the first instance an other – but, since in being negated it preserves itself at the same time, it is only being-for-other (Hegel 2010, 92/21.106).
Hegel elaborates further on this concept by looking briefly back at the
development from existence
.
First, existence
is determinacy that is maximally immediate or is in
considered first and foremost in its being
. It is not absolutely immediate
since that is what pure being
is, but maximally immediate in terms of what a being that is determinate.
Second, with the growing emphasis on non-being
that is necessarily part of
existence
, it is qualified as determinate being. Third, it is seen how this
negative element forms a negation
within itself insofar as it is regarded as a
being whose determinacy is its own as something
. Fourth, this something
is
an other
. Fifth, and consequently the present situation, this other
is
negated (though the other of the other
) but in such a way that preserves its
being as other
. The other
here ceases to be merely other
and gains a
being that is “other-for-something”, or, as Hegel terms it, being-for-other
.
In being-for-other
, the determination of something
is brought right back
into play but in terms of the other
. Put differently, determining something as
being-for-other
means that it has an existence that is for other
in the
double sense that it is, first, for “otherness” as such, and, second, that it
is for an other something
.
To illustrate, saying that the green apple appears in a certain way for me in
such and such way is really mostly in part due to the human visual field with
its particular sensitivity of the light spectrum etc., such that this
determinacy from the standpoint of the apple belongs to the other
, i.e., to
the human observer. For another observer, the apply might look very differently!
However, this other perspective cannot be wholly divorced from the apple in
question. It really belongs to the apple, at least conceptually, to be
determined in this way and picked up by an other, such that not everything about
its determining as it appears for me is exclusive only to me (lest it be a
hallucination – but then where did the first determinacy emerge from?).
Being-in-itself
It preserves itself in its non-being and is being; not, however, being in general but being with reference to itself in contrast to its reference to the other, as self-equality in contrast to its inequality. Such a being is being-in-itself (Hegel 2010, 92/21.107).
Being-in-itself
(Ansichsein) is defined in contrast to being-for-other
.
Importantly, being-in-itself
is not the immediacy of something
or its
“native” determinacy, but is specifically the determination that defines what
belongs to something
against the other
. Where the being-for-other
specifies what is open to the other
, being-in-itself
, by contrast, specifies
what is closed to the other
since it picks out what really belongs to the
something
in question. Where being-for-other
brings an unequal level of
determinacy into something
—this something
can be viewed in a plurality
of different ways according to the eye of the beholder, as it
were—being-in-itself
clears the determinacy to be only what genuinely
forms part of this something
against the other.
Take, for example, the idea that a stone has a certain hardness. This quality, however, only makes sense from the perspective of someone who can touch and compare it to other things. For the stone in itself, there is no “hard” or “soft”—only a certain resistance to being scratched or dented.
Being-for-other and Being-in-itself
Being-for-other and being-in-itself constitute the two moments of something. There are here two pairs of determinations: (1) something and other; (2) being-for-other and being-in-itself. The former contain the non-connectedness of their determinateness; something and other fall apart. But their truth is their connection; being-for-other and being-in-itself are therefore the same determinations posited as moments of one and the same unity, as determinations which are connections and which, in their unity, remain in the unity of existence. Each thus itself contains within it, at the same time, also the moment diverse from it (Hegel 2010, 92/21.107).
Two pairs of determinations are at hand. The first designates the
non-connectedness of something
and other
. Something
is only an other
implicitly, but explicitly it is in itself just something
(and vice versa
that other
is implicitly a something
). By spelling out this difference in
terms of implied and explicit, the connection between these two categories
becomes visible, such that the terms something
and other
are not sufficient
alone to determine their connection.
The second pair, then, designates the connectedness of something
and other
.
Specifically how each form moments of the same individual unity, namely, that
the same something
is also an other
(and vice versa). The inwardness and
“selfsameness” of something
is recast as being-in-itself
, designating that
which holds its own and refers to itself. Conversely, the outward and
self-negating dimension of the other
, is established as being-for-other
. The
connection is made emphatic by the fact that the both terms employ being
as
the initial ground that diffracts into its “for-otherness” and
“in-itselfness”, thus rendering each as moments of the same entity.
The extreme point of unity in the pair being-for-other
and being-in-itself
is just existence
once more, since the logic cannot collapse further back than
the category where at least two elements must co-exist (hence existence
). But
this point of unity is not really collapsed into since being-for-other
and
being-in-itself
form a pair with something
and other
whereby each contains
itself and its other.
Being-in-itself
and being-for-other
are determinations of
something
-and-other
that emphasize their connection. However, these two
determinations mirror each other in a peculiar way.
… being-in-itself is, first, negative reference to non-existence; it has otherness outside it and is opposed to it; in so far as something is in itself, it is withdrawn from being-other and being-for-other. But, second, it has non-being also right in it; for it is itself the non-being of being-for-other (Hegel 2010, 93/21.108).
Hegel points out that while being-in-itself
excludes being-for-other
, it
nonetheless refers to it—one might say, presupposes it. But Hegel goes one
step further and states that it is the non-being
of being-for-other
. This
tight coupling of being
and non-being
is reminiscent of existence
where
these two form a oneness.
A similar situation seems to be the case for being-for-other
:
But being-for-other is, first, the negation of the simple reference of being to itself which, in the first place, is supposed to be existence and something; in so far as something is in an other or for an other, it lacks a being of its own. But, second, it is not non-existence as pure nothing; it is non-existence that points to being-in-itself as its being reflected into itself, just as conversely the being-in-itself points to being-for-other (Hegel 2010, 93/21.108).
The connectedness and mutual reference of being-for-other
and
being-in-itself
shows that neither exists without the other. There is no
being-for-other
that is purely for other, since the being
it is sourced
from is its own “othering”. The same conclusion applies to being-in-itself
,
where there is no inward being which does not also determine an outward being.
These conclusions may appear uncontroversial and innocent enough, but when
turning to a more concrete reality, one often employs one without the other. One
imagines that one’s inner life of emotions and feelings is entirely
private—merely being-in-itself
—but these invariably have an
outward manifestation. Or that there is an absolute law of nature that merely
exists in itself without reference to its expression in things. Or, conversely,
that one can put up a certain manner of being pretending that is not who one is,
for example, “this job is not who I am, it is only something I do while I wait
for better things” or “I only do this to be nice to you, but it is not who I
am”. Or that money only has an apparent, illusory value but no intrinsic value
whatsoever. If Hegel is right, there really is no being-in-itself
that does
not also have a being-for-other
and vice versa. The two point to one and the
same concept.
Looking back at the development of the Logic, pure being
has failed to be in
its sheer immediacy. Instead, being exists in being determinate. This
determinacy has now evolved to the point where it subsists as self-referring
being or something
. But this self-reference precisely excludes the other
,
rendering something
in more precise terms as being-in-itself
—the
being
that refers to itself through excluding non-being
. But determinacy
requires the element of non-being
as a moment of the self-referring being.
Indeed, where pure being
fails to be, something
succeeds by its ability to
refer to itself by excluding—or negating
—non-being
from
itself. This exclusion is the being-for-other
that opens up the
something
’s being-in-itself
. This concept applies no less to the entire
logic itself up to this point. In other words, logic has a being-in-itself
that is its own—it does not belong to any one human language, individual
thought or symbolic expression—but it has a being that is presentable
through all languages, thoughts and expressions—but the conclusion forces
us to recognize that logic is only meaningful, paradoxically, in being negated.
Something Undivided
Both moments are determinations of one and the same, namely of something. Something is in-itself in so far as it has returned from the being-for-other back to itself. But something has also a determination or circumstance, whether in itself [an sich] (here the accent is on the in) or in it [an ihm]; in so far as this circumstance is in it [an ihm] externally, it is a being-for-other (Hegel 2010, 93/21.108).
Hegel here differentiates between, on the one hand, what something is in itself,
without relation to anything else, and, on the other hand, something happening
on or with respect to a specific thing. For example, Kant’s notion of Das Ding
an sich (the thing in itself), designates the thing that is beyond our
perception, merely as it is in itself. Conversely, man kann das an ihm
erkennen (you can recognize that in him—or on him), points to something
related to or happening with a particular thing—something
in an
other
.
This leads to a further determination. Being-in-itself and being-for-other are different at first. But that something also has in it what it is in itself and conversely is in itself also what it is as being-for-other — this is the identity of being-in-itself and being-for-other, in accordance with the determination that the something is itself one and the same something of both moments, and these are in it, therefore, undivided (Hegel 2010, 93/21.108).
It was understood earlier that being-in-itself
and being-for-other
form part
of the same something
. Here Hegel emphasizes the point through the double
meaning of in it (an sich and an ihm) which inheres in both
determinations: First, in it (an sich) in the absolute sense signifies the
being-in-itself
of something
—its own closed interior and exclusive
ownership. Second, in it (an ihm) in the relative sense signifies the
being-for-other
of something
—the determination of it open to others
and, one might say, shared ownership. However, both terms are determinations of
the same something
or, by happy coincidence of language, share the same in
it, and in that respect the same something
inheres in both.
By virtue of this identity, what first appeared as different terms are in fact the same.
In the unity of the something with itself, being-for-other is identical with its in-itself; the being-for-other is thus in the something. The determinateness thus reflected into itself is therefore again a simple existent and hence again a quality – determination (Hegel 2010, 95/21.110).
Once it is understood that being-in-itself
and being-for-other
are of the
same something
—here something
is regarded in its self-reference, or
“unity with itself”—the terms converge since being-for-other
does not
exist apart from something
but is immanent to it, and in that regard, it is
equally its being-in-itself
. Likewise, being-in-itself
must also be an
“expression” of something
inasmuch as the interiority is distinguished
vis-à-vis exteriority; but this expression precisely determined what belongs to
the something
in question, and so the determinateness of the exterior here is
nothing separate from the interior and the two once more converge. In other
words, insofar as something
is concerned in pure terms of being-in-itself
and being-for-other
, the exterior is the interior and vice versa.
Reciprocal Determination? (Niklas)
By virtue of the identity in something
, being-in-itself
and
being-for-other
are different expressions of the same. However, Hegel’s
transition may not be entirely exhaustive, since there remains the logical
possibility that these terms reciprocally determine one another which may yield
a different dialectical outcome.
First, it must be established that something
in the development of the Logic
proves have determinations that are expressed to others. Indeed, these
determinations that are expressed to other are integral to the something
actually having determinations of its own. Hegel criticizes Kant’s notion of a
thing-in-itself
since it stipulates a something
that has no such expressed
determinations, which is incoherent.
Things are called “in-themselves” in so far as abstraction is made from all being-for-other, which really means, in so far as they are thought without all determination, as nothing. In this sense, of course, it is impossible to know what the thing-in-itself is. For the question “what?” calls for determinations to be produced; but since the things of which the determinations are called for are at the same time presumed to be things-in-themselves, which means precisely without determination, the impossibility of an answer is thoughtlessly implanted in the question, or else a senseless answer is given (Hegel 2010, 94/21.109).
Therefore, something
must have being-for-other
. Something
is a form of
determinate being that not only specifies what determinacy minimally is, but
what determinacy must minimally be in order to make available to others what
really belongs to it, i.e. a determinacy that is split between its
being-in-itself
and being-for-other
.
So, with the identity of the terms in mind, one can take it further since
being-in-itself
and being-for-other
reciprocally determine one another
insofar as each is a being-in-itself
of the same something
in forming
moments of it, and, likewise, each is an expression, a being-for-other
, of the
same something
insofar as they make available a determination of that
something
. Thus, both being-in-itself
and being-for-other
take turns, as
it were, in being for another and being in itself for the being that has any
determinations of its own. This does not, however, appear develop any new
results, but repeats the pattern already established. If anything, it reinforces
the identity of the terms such that neither can be the sole context of both
itself and the other; such that a further determination lies at the seams.
The implications of this is not that being-in-itself
and being-for-other
are
untrue or erroneous. However, they are erroneous if one is taken to be true
without the other, that is, if one is held to be true unconditionally and
absolutely. As Hegel shows in his critique of Kant, an incoherence exists
immediately in the idea of a thing-in-itself
, since one stipulates something
that has no being-for-other
, but this leaves out exactly the very
determination thing-in-itself, such that there exists at least one
determination, namely, the one that brings forth its being-in-itself
.
Further Commentary
Houlgate
Stephen Houlgate emphasizes that while the term “other” has been used in the
Logic up to this point, such as being
and nothing
each being unseparated
from its other, neither of these (nor reality
or negation
) are actually
other
to each other. The other
, Houlgate writes,
is not just simple negation … it is self-relating negation. Unlike negation, therefore the other is not merely one side of a difference: it is not bound to something in the way negation is bound to reality. Rather, the other stands apart from something as something separate from it, as something of its own (Houlgate 2022, 177).
Like reality
and negation
, something
and other
co-exist while being
different, yet their difference is not merely two sides of the same difference
(moments of a difference) but are self-relating distinctions. “Being other
than something thus consists in being separate from it, not in being its simple
negation” (Houlgate 2022, 177).
With regards to something
and other
as such, Houlgate notes that a certain
indeterminacy is at play. Neither is fixed as this something
and not that.
However, this indeterminacy is different from that of being
and nothing
as
something
and other
do not vanish into one another but each are, rather, the
other in being itself (see Houlgate 2022, 179).
However, a subtle shift has taken place. Other
is a determination that not
only applies to the other
but can equally apply to something
. The
determination of other
itself has become “alien” (fremd), belonging to
neither. Houlgate continues:
This is because each is now a something and is determined to be other only by the presence outside it of its counterpart. Being other still means being a self- relating negation, that is, being the negation of something and yet standing apart from the latter as something in its own right. Now, however, neither of the somethings is intrinsically other, but each is other only because there is something for it to be other than. If, therefore, either – > per impossibile – were to be all on its own, it would not be an other, but would simply be self-relating being, or something. It is only the presence of a second something that turns each into an “other” (Houlgate 2022, 179).
This does not make other
a contingent determination that something
may or
may not exhibit, Houlgate adds, but the other
follows logically from being
something
. However, it is “only thanks to its other that something is an other
itself”. As an aside, it does appear as if other
is qualified upon the
determination of the second something
. This aligns with Houlgate’s
conclusion that it belongs to the very nature of something
to be one of (at
least) two.
In the other
relating negatively to itself, a new form of becoming
becoming-other
is made explicit. This new becoming is more aptly understood as
change. Furthermore, it is discovered that this logical form of change does
not presuppose time.
Houlgate points out that, through change, something
gains stronger terms of
differentiation vis-à-vis other
. Since something
now becomes understood to
exclude otherness both within itself and outside itself. Because of this,
Houlgate writes, “otherness now lies both within and outside the something, the
latter is not-other, or not-the-other, in two senses: it is not the other or
otherness that constitutes it, but also not the other that stands apart from
it” (Houlgate 2022, 186). This is because, through the process of change, the
other
that is other to itself that proves to be something
, becomes this new
something
not merely as an instance of that other's
“othering”, such that
the something
at hand ceases to be purely other
– it is more overtly
negative – it is not just that other.
Two new senses develop from this. Firstly, something
and other
are no longer
simply reversible. Now, Houlgate highlights, “something differs from being-other
in such a way that the latter does not belong to it. Something is now
definitely something, not other itself or the other outside it” (Houlgate
2022, 186). Secondly, the two categories are now more explicitly connected to
each other. Something
is no longer “something as such” but
something-that-is-not-the-other
; and the other
, initially separate, becomes
a connected moment of something
. Something
, Houlgate states, thus has a
double-edged character: “it is both distinguished from and connected to the
other by not being that other” (Houlgate 2022, 186-7).
From this, the implication that the other
is built into something
, the two
thus stand in explicit relation. The name given to the fact that something
is
related to other
is being-for-other
. Here Houlgate notes that the
preposition “for” does not indicate that something is at the disposal of the
other or for the latter’s benefit, but, rather, a shorthand for
“related-to”—“being-related-to-other”. Moreover, something
is not
related to an other
because there is some other out there, but because
other-relatedness is part of the nature of being something
.
But something
is also self-relating, in a way that is quite different and
unconnected to the other
, which is termed being-in-itself
(Ansichsein).
This is quite different from being-within-itself
(Insichsein). “The latter
is simply self-relating being, or something, as such; being-in-itself, on the
other hand, is one aspect or side of something: something as self-related
rather than other-related. Indeed, Hegel maintains, a thing’s being-in-itself
is explicitly opposed to its other-relatedness” (Houlgate 2022, 188).
Further to being-in-itself
, Houlgate comments that it is a subtle fusion of
separateness and relatedness. For, on the one hand, being-in-itself
expressly
excludes all otherness and is the something
that relates purely to itself. On
the other hand, however, being-in-itself
opposes relations to other, and by
the virtue of this opposition remains related to being-for-other
. This fusion
is “expressed in the thought that being-in-itself is being that has ‘withdrawn
from being-other and being-for-other’” (Houlgate 2022, 188, emphasis added). A
withdrawal that cannot be logically separated from what it withdraws from.
Being-in-itself
and being-for-other
are each inextricably tied to one
another in something
, but unlike reality
and negation
in existence
,
these moments do not conceal each other but explicitly point to the other from
which it is separate (see Houlgate 2022, 189). This forms the groundwork of a
critique of Kant’s thing in itself.
Bibliography
- Hegel, G.W.F. 2010. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Science of Logic. Translated by George Di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Houlgate, S. 2022. Hegel on Being. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
Authors
Filip Niklas (2025)