The Development of Becoming
The Unity of Being and Nothing
Pure being and pure nothing are therefore the same. The truth is neither being nor nothing, but rather that being has passed over into nothing and nothing into being - “has passed over,” not passes over. But the truth is just as much that they are not without distinction; it is rather that they are not the same, that they are absolutely distinct yet equally unseparated and inseparable, and that each immediately vanishes in its opposite. Their truth is therefore this movement of the immediate vanishing of the one into the other: becoming, a movement in which the two are distinguished, but by a distinction which has just as immediately dissolved itself (Hegel 2010, 60-61/21.69-70).
The development of becoming
picks up on the discovery made with the categories
being
and
nothing
, namely, that being
and nothing
have no distinguishing factor. As discussed elsewhere, there is a
difference between being
and nothing
but it is only an immediate difference.
Hegel begins by pointing out that neither being
nor nothing
are stable
categories that simply exist, but that they each pass over into the other. The
truth of the matter is, then, that there is no such thing as pure being
simpliciter that does not turn out to disappear into nothing
(and vice
versa). This emphasizes the inseparability of the two categories.
Hegel then points out that these categories really are distinct. Being
and
nothing
are different conceptions, and this difference is important in
understanding the movement of becoming
. It is insofar as being
and nothing
pass over into each other—or vanish into its opposite—that a
movement has begun to take shape.
It is seen here how the immediate vanishing of being
and nothing
play a role
in forming an idea of movement which contains both the inseparability and
difference of the two categories. This “movement” of becoming
establishes
something of a third element that groups the other two under a new identity, but
as already visible from the end of the quote, this unity is highly unstable.
Additionally, the term “vanishing” first appears here and is used extensively to convey the passing of one category to the other as both immediate and absolute. There is no further or deeper sub-process or mediation to deign here. Neither is the passage partial or piecemeal; when one category vanishes into another its disappearance is instantaneous and total.
The Moments of Becoming
Inseparability
Becoming is the unseparatedness of being and nothing, not the unity that abstracts from being and nothing; as the unity of being and nothing it is rather this determinate unity, or one in which being and nothing equally are. However, inasmuch as being and nothing are each unseparated from its other, each is not. In this unity, therefore, they are, but as vanishing, only as sublated. They sink from their initially represented self-subsistence into moments which are still distinguished but at the same time sublated (Hegel 2010, 80/21.92).
Here Hegel stresses that becoming
is not to be understood as just a static
unity that merely combines being
and nothing
side-by-side without taking
into account the nuances of their respective developments. Inasmuch as
becoming
is regarded as the unity of the two categories it has specifically to
do with their inseparability.
However, this inseparability needs to be further qualified. If each category is isolated with this inseparability, then it is negated on account that it does not have any self-subsistence, reality or independence vis-Ă -vis the other it is inseparable from.
Therefore, the unity of becoming
contains both categories as moments. This
sublated state does double work: first, it ensures the distinctiveness of each
category; second, it also illustrates their inseparability through the shared
context.
Put differently, the developments of being
and nothing
lead to divergent
results: on the one hand, each is an immediate self-subsistent category totally
distinct from the other, but, on the other hand, each is indistinguishable from
the other and vanishes into that other, implying an undeniable inseparability.
This looks like a problem: How can these results be coherently understood
together? Becoming
is the category that creatively combines these two results
through the idea of “moment”: a logic that at once joins together while it
differentiates.
Before proceeding, it is worthwhile to note that, strictly speaking, negation
at this stage of the Logic has not been developed. It does not, however, drive
the logic forward because it is used under a conditional that serves to
illustrate a wrong case, viz. isolating being
or nothing
concerning their
inseparability. Instead, the inseparability in question occurs exactly within a
higher-level context, namely, that of becoming
.
Another thing to note is that it might be confusing, or counter-intuitive that
being
and nothing
are understood to be independent whilst in a determinate
unity. This is part of the development of becoming
where the issue is to
understand two terms as both identical and different. An issue yet to resolved.
Unequal Passage
Grasped as thus distinguished, each is in their distinguishedness a unity with the other. Becoming thus contains being and nothing as two such unities, each of which is itself unity of being and nothing; the one is being as immediate and as reference to nothing; the other is nothing as immediate and as reference to being; in these unities the determinations are of unequal value (Hegel 2010, 80/21.93).
Hegel explores the inseparability of being
and nothing
further from two
different vantage points. Why two? Because the main context of becoming
that
unifies these two categories does not establish an abstract, static unity where
the two are merely side-by-side, since that does not account for their nuances.
Here we see those nuances become explicit in the thought that being and
nothing is not equal to nothing and being. How is this so?
Initially, back in the earlier developments of being
and nothing
, each
simply is or turns out to be the same as the other. Now, it is understood
that being
vanishes into nothing
. In this context of becoming
, the two
categories become regarded as one “passing into another”, but this still
requires that one is a starting point and the other is the target. In other
words, the thought demands one is immediate and the other is the reference.
While this pattern of “passing into another” is valid for both, it plays out
very differently whether it is being
that passes into nothing
, or nothing
that passes into being. This is why Hegel states that the determinations in
these unities are of unequal value.
Once again, it is worth noting that Hegel has been using determinate-
and
determination
in this section, and, like negation
, these are terms not
explicitly developed in the logic. Unlike negation
, however, the terms at hand
seem to do more work for the argument. On the one hand, determination here may
not be used in a technical sense and merely makes the difference between being
and nothing
more poignant. On the other hand, however, the term stresses drive
and resolution, and a sharp unity of fixed difference, which prefigures a later
category. Its usage here is somewhat misleading, if not problematic, and Hegel
could quite easily have replaced it with less technically charged words without
affecting the argument.
Emergence and Cessation
Becoming is in this way doubly determined. In one determination, nothing is the immediate, that is, the determination begins with nothing and this refers to being; that is to say, it passes over into it. In the other determination, being is the immediate, that is, the determination begins with being and this passes over into nothing – coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be (Hegel 2010, 80/21.93).
The two unities of being
and nothing
are recast into coming-to-be and
ceasing-to-be based on which direction the passage occurs. The unequal value of
these passages is perhaps more clear now in the rephrasing, since it spells out
that it is being, in both accounts (coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be), which
either arrives or departs.
What is key is that Hegel relates this back to becoming
. It is in the context
of movement that the inseparability of the two categories is made explicit, and
any further details discovered will reflect back on this context.
A possible complication to the logic is that the coming-to-be and
ceasing-to-be—which currently is defined with the vanishing of being
into nothing
and nothing
into being
respectively—could be equally
applied over the category nothing
itself. That is to say, nothing
could be
coming-to-be where its self-subsistence as nothing concerned and
creasing-to-be when it vanishes into being
. This idea, while tempting at
first, is not really coherent. Firstly, it presupposes the original coming-to-be
and ceasing-to-be vis-Ă -vis being
and nothing
; secondly, it breaks the
definition of nothing
as the absolute absence of being
, which is required
for the original movement. Therefore, the coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be cannot
apply to nothing
except in a very abstract or non-substantive sense.
Mutual Paralysis
Both are the same, becoming, and even as directions that are so different they interpenetrate and paralyze each other. The one is ceasing-to-be; being passes over into nothing, but nothing is just as much the opposite of itself, the passing-over into being, coming-to-be. This coming-to-be is the other direction; nothing goes over into being, but being equally sublates itself and is rather the passing-over into nothing; it is ceasing-to-be. – They do not sublate themselves reciprocally – the one sublating the other externally – but each rather sublates itself in itself and is within it the opposite of itself (Hegel 2010, 80-1/21.93).
While two specific movements of coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be point in opposite
directions, they fold into same becoming
and come to mirror the initial
inseparability that defined being
and nothing
.
Importantly, the source of each specific movement is in the root category in
question and there is no external action or cause that the made the category
operate in the way that it did, namely, that it vanished into its other. Putting
it plainly, being
is ceasing-to-be as it vanishes into nothing
, but
likewise nothing
is coming-to-be as it vanishes into being
.
In addition, Hegel writes that the two specific movements interpenetrate and paralyze each other. How do they relate and why would they paralyze each other?
In the first place, the two specific movements relate because they are of the
same inseparability; the same becoming
defines coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be.
Once this is understood, the issue with their opposite movements should become
clear, namely, the same becoming
is a movement both of coming-to-be and
ceasing-to-be. Recall that for pure being
and nothing
, their vanishing is
total and absolute, and occurs immediately. Indeed, the vanishing is so
immediate that Hegel indicates it by stating it is
not passing but has passed. As the categories
are this unstable, effectively coming-to-be is ceasing-to-be, and
ceasing-to-be is coming-to-be—emergence and cessation occur
simultaneously within the same context. Therefore, becoming
, if Hegel is
right, is a double movement of rising and falling.
Sublation of Becoming
Quiescent Result and Destruction
The equilibrium in which coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be are poised is in the first place becoming itself. But this becoming equally collects itself in quiescent unity. Being and nothing are in it only as vanishing; becoming itself, however, is only by virtue of their being distinguished. Their vanish- ing is therefore the vanishing of becoming, or the vanishing of the vanishing itself. Becoming is a ceaseless unrest that collapses into a quiescent result (Hegel 2010, 81/21.93).
Hegel goes into more detail here on how coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be paralyze
not only each other but the unity that constitutes them. Importantly, he points
out how becoming
depends on the difference between being
and nothing
,
but as it has been understood, this difference itself immediately dissolves
since there is nothing determinate to support it. In other words, the difference
itself emerges as it ceases. Given that the moments of becoming
lose their
difference, the dependencies of the movement are gone and with it becoming
collapses into a quiescent result.
Put differently, becoming
depends on the vanishing of being
and nothing
,
but this vanishing is itself unsustainable and thus vanishes, hence Hegel’s
phrase “the vanishing of the vanishing”.
This can also be expressed thus: becoming is the vanishing of being into nothing, and of nothing into being, and the vanishing of being and nothing in general; but at the same time it rests on their being distinct. It therefore contradicts itself in itself, because what it unites within itself is self-opposed; but such a union destroys itself (Hegel 2010, 81/21.93-4).
Hegel repeats the point, but sharpens the idea of an internal opposition within
becoming
itself. Its movement brings together contradictory impulses and is
torn asunder by the unrelenting indeterminacy of pure being
and nothing
.
Becoming
is the attempt, one might say, to bring some coherence to the
conflicting motions of the early categories by carefully noting what must be the
case: being
and nothing
are different, they are the same and they vanish
into one another. The tools by which becoming
puts these divergent and
incompatible ideas, such as moments, movement, coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be,
are innovative and creative, but equally cannot contain the fury of negativity
latent within them. Becoming
itself thus emerges and perishes.
Not Nothing
This result is a vanishedness, but it is not nothing; as such, it would be only a relapse into one of the already sublated determinations and not the result of nothing and of being. It is the unity of being and nothing that has become quiescent simplicity. But this quiescent simplicity is being, yet no longer for itself but as determination of the whole (Hegel 2010, 81/21.94).
The vanishing of the vanishing would return one to the category nothing
, but
Hegel claims that this is not so. The first reason is that this would only put
the logic back a few steps and those steps would lead precisely back to the
present circumstance. Now, it may be that the logic merely loops around
endlessly between nothing
and becoming
from this point on, but even this
loop would be a new result, and one that displays characteristics of stability
not seen before. The second reason is that this relapse does not take into
account the complete outcome of being
and nothing
, viz. how they are
inseparable.
It is exactly this inseparability that is left after the rise and fall of
becoming
: the vanishing of being
and nothing
cannot be coherently
determined since it itself vanishes, but it remains a fact that these two pure
categories are deeply entangled and the motion of their vanishing is matched
only by the inertia of their belonging.
Being
and nothing
are thus understood to be simply together, but this
togetherness itself falls under the header of being
since this unity is. As
seen above with the specific movements, it is being
that comes-to-be and
ceases-to-be. Now a new being must be defined, since the being of being
and
nothing
is no longer pure.
Stepping Out
Becoming, as transition into the unity of being and nothing, a unity which is as existent or has the shape of the one-sided immediate unity of these moments, is existence (Hegel 2010, 81/21.94).
The being of being
and nothing
is existence
(determinate being
). It
designates a new immediacy but minimally determinate since it presents at once a
combination of different moments. The moments of becoming
, by contrast, had to
be mediated through the context of inseparability. And it can be seen here how
existence
is the real becoming of becoming
, as the movement of the latter
turned out to be the process that engendered the being that was moved. Thus,
becoming
cannot logically be at rest with itself. Like its preceding
categories, it cannot remain pure and vanishes into what determined itself.
If Hegel is right, pure becoming
is an incoherent and incomplete idea, or
there is no such thing, ontologically, as simple becoming. And while existence
may turn out to be many things, both in the Logic and elsewhere in philosophy
and beyond, it cannot be anything less than that which is both being
and
nothing
.
Further Commentary
Burbidge
John Burbidge’s analysis of becoming
begins from the thought that being
and
nothing
cannot be held in isolation, as discrete abstractions. Failing to hold
these absolutely different, they are brought to relation and this forces the
understanding to examine this reference: “The only way the difference can be
maintained is through reference to the process of thought itself. For it alone
indicates that they are not simply identical” (Burbidge 1981, 40).
The difference and sameness of being
and nothing
constitute two aspects that
are brought together in a synthetic relationship of unity and difference. What
is important here is that the independence of both categories is in favor of
being retained as moments. Burbidge names the movement of being
to nothing
genesis, and the converse movement perishing (Burbidge 1981, 41). And as
each movement completes, it is itself transformed to its opposite: perishing
dissolves into a new process of genesis and genesis into perishing. They are
both, however, moments of the overall category becoming
, and so form a double
process.
Burbidge writes that becoming
depends on being
and nothing
to be perfectly
different and that it ceases if they are understood to be the same. However,
becoming
depends on being
and nothing
being both perfectly different
and exactly the same. The contradiction of becoming
is rather that its very
process turns them from their absolute vanishing—which is derived from
their immediate difference and sameness—into related moments.
The result of the mediation of becoming
is brought about by thought moving to
a new perspective that grasps that being
and nothing
are not simply
opposites but are “subcontraries of a more inclusive category”, which, by virtue
of being an intellectual concept, Burbidge asserts “must be” (Burbidge 1981,
41). The collapse of becoming
into this unity Burbidge names “a being”
[Dasein], as he goes on to write: “The indefinite article suggests that it is
not absolutely indeterminate but is in some way limited by a nothing out of
which it comes and to which it may return” (Burbidge 1981, 42).
Burbidge’s decision to name Dasein “a being” is puzzling and his reasoning for
it is less clear. The term relies on implicit assumptions rather than
designating a well defined meaning; “a being” may well suggest that it is not
absolutely indeterminate, but it also suggests that it is one being among many,
which is something Dasein, or Existence
, definitely is not. Unfortunately,
the term Burbidge chose pollutes the thought of the logic rather than clarifying
it.
Houlgate
With the category becoming
Hegel has reached the standpoint of Heraclitus,
where everything flows and all is becoming (Houlgate 2022, 147). Stephen
Houlgate contends that at this point in the Logic, Hegel fully affirms a
Heraclitean vision of a ceaselessly changing reality; Hegel “is affirming a
Heraclitean vision of sheer becoming” (Houlgate 2022, 147). Importantly,
though, Houlgate points out that Hegel shows us this Heraclitean vision by the
standpoint of Parmenides, namely, the standpoint of pure being
(although
Parmenides himself would never leave his standpoint).
The becoming
Hegel examines, however, is not a becoming understood to occur
in time. Rather, it is only the transition of pure being
and nothing
into
one another. As human thinkers, we need time to think this transition; but
pure being
does not prove to be nothing
in virtue of time passing, but in
virtue of what turns out to be logically the case conceptually.
…the process, described in logic, in which being proves to be becoming (and then further forms of being) is not temporal … It is the logical process in which being discloses what it is in truth. Hegel’s claim is thus not that in time there is first being, then nothing and then becoming, but that logically being itself proves to be becoming (as it will later prove to be substance, the Idea and space-time)(Houlgate 2022, 148).
In Houlgate’s reading, the categories being
and nothing
undergo a twofold
transformation, namely, turning into processes of which they are themselves
moments. Nothing
does not simply vanish into being
, but proves to be that
vanishing, the very transition into its opposite. In that sense, it proves to be
the process of coming-to-be.
In this process of nothing
, nothing
itself is immediate and passes over
into being
, such that the process itself contains nothing
and being
as its
two moments. The same holds for the process of being
. “As becoming, therefore,
being and nothing are the process of vanishing itself; but, as moments of
becoming, they are each that which vanishes into the other” (Houlgate 2022,
149). In Houlgate’s understanding, then, being
and nothing
are each seen
both as the process of vanishing (or becoming) and as moments of the
vanishing, respectively.
In Houlgate’s estimate, becoming
inaugurates a more stable thought, albeit one
of restless instability. His point, however, is that the thought of becoming
does not immediately vanish into another category, as with being
and
nothing
. This requires a more active participation by thought in order to
uncover what is immanent in the category. However, Houlgate warns that this does
not make the logic something “artificially engineered by us”, but made necessary
by what is inherent in becoming
itself (Houlgate 2022, 150). Indeed, as
revealed in the examination of the development,
becoming
does not immediately turn into something else but spawns a process of
becoming
.
The exact nature of the vanishing of being
and nothing
, which is key to
understanding becoming
, is in recognizing that being
and nothing
, Houlgate
writes, “cannot merely vanish into one another – for in that way, they
do not actually vanish – but must vanish into their both having
vanished” (Houlgate 2022, 151). The result of this vanishing of the vanishing
can itself neither be pure being
nor pure nothing
—since that exactly
returns the vanishing—but one where a unity or inseparability of being
and nothing
where their purity and pure immediate difference have been
annihilated.
The movement of becoming
requires this very purity and difference, however,
and without it, becoming
itself is brought to a halt. But it is becoming
itself which brings about this halting. In a manner of speaking, it is a
process that is generated by a source but within that generation the source
altered and the process itself ceases, leaving the altered source. As Houlgate
concludes, “We move forward from becoming to determinate being, therefore, not
because we prefer stability over instability, but because we take seriously the
loss of purity that is only inadequately embodied in becoming” (Houlgate 2022,
152).
Surprisingly, then, the problem with Heraclitean becoming
from Hegel’s point
of view, according to Houlgate, is not that it denies the purity of Parmenidean
being
but that it actually clings to it all too firmly. Becoming
feeds off
the purity of being
—and in some respects, mimics it—since it
requires the loss and re-emergence of it; in becoming
, pure being
is
contained intact. Both philosophers fail to see that, logically, pure being
must transform itself to determinate existence
, where no purity is the case
at all (Houlgate 2022, 152).
McTaggart
John McTaggart aptly puts it that being
and nothing
only exist in becoming
as disappearing moments, but that these very moments must be separate, for, “if
they are not separate, how can they pass into one another” (McTaggart 1910, 17).
McTaggart thinks that becoming
was inadequately named by Hegel, since he
contends that this term is too concrete and that it brings with it too many
unwanted connotations. He suggests that the synthesis (his term) of being
and
nothing
should have been named “transition to being determinate” [Übergang
in das Dasein] (McTaggart 1910, 20), pointing to the precedent Hegel set in the
case of the last category of measure
, called “transition to essence”. What are
McTaggart’s reasons for this claim? Why is “becoming” inadequate?
In order to better understand McTaggart’s standpoint, it must first be
understood that he maintains that being
is dependent on nothing
in order
that it should be being
and vice versa.
In other words, a category of Being without Nothing, or of Nothing without Being, is inadequate and leads to contradictions which prove its falsity. The only truth of the two is a category which expresses the relation of the two (McTaggart 1910, 17).
There is no contradiction in the union of being
and nothing
, at least not in
the manner seen in the development of becoming
concerning their exact identity
and pure difference.
Now, the issues McTaggart sees in the term “becoming”, are specifically:
- The term “becoming” evokes the idea of a process of change. A change of something to something else.
- Change, in turn, involves the existence of some permanent element in what changes. An element that does not change. Put differently, change requires some stable form to contrast the contends that were changed.
- It is impossible in the categories of
being
andnothing
, since there is no room for distinction between a changing and an unchanging layer of reality as the categories are simply undifferentiated. - Therefore, if something should be capable of change, it must be analyzable into two elements, one which does not change. “This is impossible under the categories of Quality”, McTaggart claims (McTaggart 1910, 17).
McTaggart considers the scenario that becoming
may not be a fully developed
sense of change, but change in a more rudimentary form. Rather than change of A
into B, it is the disappearance of A and the appearance of B. But McTaggart
thinks that even in the latter case, when carefully analyzed, would “involve the
presence of some element which persisted unchanged in connection first with A
and then B”, and that would just be change proper (McTaggart 1910, 19).
Furthermore, McTaggart contends that the essence of the new category
(existence
) is in the necessary implication of being
and nothing
and “not
in any change taking place between them” (McTaggart 1910, 19).
Reviewing McTaggart’s commentary on becoming
, it appears to deal more with
possible semantic implications rather than with the technicalities of the
argument, which problematizes his reading. Here are a few points to consider.
- Firstly, nowhere does Hegel employ “change” to describe the movement of
becoming
; rather, he carefully combines ideas of “vanishing”. So while McTaggart is right that change requires some permanent element, and therefore does not map on to the logic ofbecoming
, it was never asked for by the argument of the Logic. Instead, it is better to think ofbecoming
not as any species of change but simply as becoming, a unique logical movement. - Secondly, McTaggart’s understanding that
existence
is merely the necessary implication ofbeing
andnothing
, omits the important point that these can no longer be thought in their purity (see Houlgate’s commentary on this). - Thirdly, misnaming
becoming
with preference for the much more generic “transition to determinate being”, while not relevant to the logic, would miss out on the historical debt being paid to Heraclitus and could therefore make the category less accessible.
Against McTaggart, then, the question of change is taken up later in the
Logic, when the categories of determination
, constitution
and limit
become explicit. In becoming
, by contrast, the issue is rather about
explicating vanishing and pure, radical movement, which may later factor into
the idea of change but in no way, logically, presuppose it.
Bibliography
- Hegel, G.W.F. 2010. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Science of Logic. Translated by George Di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Burbidge, J.W. 1981. On Hegel’s Logic: Fragments of a Commentary. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press.
- Houlgate, S. 2022. Hegel on Being. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
- McTaggart, J.M.E. 1910. A Commentary on Hegel’s Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Authors
Filip Niklas (2024)
Editors
Ahilleas Rokni (2024)