A. The Mechanical Object: Section 3
In Section 3 of A. The Mechanical Object, Hegel builds on the analysis of the infinite regress of determinism, because, as Hegel will go on to show, determinism leads to a contradiction that must be resolved. It is this contradiction that will lead us to the next chapter of Mechanism.
We have already said that there is no moment of self-determination within the
mechanical objects
. Instead, the determinateness that lies between them is
entirely external and, owing to their indifference, entirely indeterminate. As
such, the determinateness that lies between each mechanical object
is
identical to every other. To clarify, the determinateness is identical because
there is no specific determination given to the determinateness by a particular
mechanical object
. If every mechanical object
is entirely indifferent to
every other mechanical object
, then the determinateness that lies between them
is simply that: the external determinateness between two indifferent and
indeterminate mechanical objects
. That determinateness is identical for each
mechanical object
. So whether you have a rock slamming into a rock, or a rock
falling into the water, there is no determinate difference. In both cases, we
are basically talking about an external determinateness between two indifferent
and indeterminate mechanical objects
. This is what is going on in the first
half of Section 3:
Now as the determinateness of an object lies in an other, no determinate difference is to be found between them; the determinateness is merely doubled, once in one object and again in the other, something utterly identical, so that the explanation or comprehension is tautological. This tautology is an external futile see-saw; since the determinateness obtains from the objects which are indifferent to it no peculiar distinctiveness and is therefore only identical, there is before us only one determinateness; and its being doubled expresses just this externality and nullity of a difference (Hegel 1991, 714).
For Hegel, the chain of external, indifferent, determinateness between
mechanical objects
is a mere tautology, which means that there is really only
one determinateness throughout the chain of external determinateness. This is,
more or less, a repetition of the point made in Section 2 when we were
discussing Hegel’s account of determinism.
Now, the identity of the determinateness (and as my example above should have
made clear) effectively means that we treat each mechanical object
as no
different to any other mechanical object
. If the particular
mechanical object
does not contribute any of its own particular
determinateness in its relation to other objects, and if it is only the external
determinateness of objects that exists between objects, then there is no
meaningful distinction between the interaction of different
mechanical objects
. This, whilst being true for the mechanical objects
,
nevertheless, leads to a contradiction because the mechanical objects
are not
merely identical. They are each a totality that is indifferent to every other
mechanical object
and so not simply the same as every other
mechanical object
. Thus, despite having an identical determinateness they
remain different mechanical objects
. Herein lies the contradiction of the
mechanical object
. This is what Hegel has to say on this:
Here, then, we have the manifest contradiction between the complete mutual indifference of the objects and the identity of their determinateness, or the contradiction of their complete externality in the identity of their determinateness (Hegel 1991, 713).
To return to my example of the rock that splashes into the water. From a
mechanistic perspective, it makes not a bit of difference whether it is a rock
or a boulder that splashed into the water because the determinateness of the
mechanical objects is identical. This identity of determinateness has the effect
of treating the mechanical objects
as interchangeable because, with regard to
their external determinateness, there is no distinction between one or the
other. However, this is to ignore another equally crucial determination of the
mechanical objects
: their indifference. How can two objects be treated as
identical whilst being indifferent to each other? Hegel’s response is that that
is exactly where the logic of Mechanism leads us - towards the contradiction
that the determinateness of a mechanical object
is both identical to every
other mechanical object
whilst the object itself being indifferent to that
very identical determinateness. This contradiction, then, is comprehended and
grasped as the negative unity of the mechanical objects
:
This contradiction is, therefore, the negative unity of a number of objects which, in that unity, simply repel one another: this is the mechanical process (Hegel 1991, 713).
The conclusion of the A. The Mechanical Object, then, is that these
mechanical objects
that were initially taken as immediately identical,
indeterminate, and indifferent, are in fact in a contradiction with each other.
This contradiction is a negative unity whereby what it is for a
mechanical object
to be itself is for its determinateness to be identical to
the determinateness of other mechanical objects
(the unity of the negative
unity), whilst for it to be indifferent to other mechanical objects
(the
negative in negative unity). This new unity takes us into the next chapter of
Mechanism, B. The Mechanical Process.
Bibliography
- Hegel, G.W.F. 1991. Hegel’s Science of Logic. Translated by A.V. Miller. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press.
Authors
Ahilleas Rokni (2024)
Contributors
Filip Niklas (2024)