Change Without Time
Hegel’s account of something
and other
develops a minimal idea of change
through becoming-other
, which differs from sheer
becoming
. This conception of
change is provocative since it is an idea of change that does not presuppose
time.
This article builds on the
development of
something
and other
, and it is strongly recommended to read it first.
During the
development of
something
and other
, Stephen Houlgate notes that the other
must also be
negatively related to itself. “Its self-relation must,” Houlgate writes,
“consist in self-negation, or in being other than itself” (Houlgate 2022,
181). This process of “becoming other” is called “change” or “alteration”: “The
nature of the other”, Houlgate continues, “is not only to stand apart from
another thing, but also, in so doing, to change” (Houlgate 2022, 181). In this
respect, the logical development once more proves to be more dynamic rather than
settled and stable. A new form of “becoming” has been re-introduced by the
other
; a “becoming” of becoming-other
or of “othering” oneself.
This process is inherent in the very nature of the other and, since every something is also an other, inherent in the nature of something, too. According to Hegel’s logic, therefore, there must be determinate being in the form of something, but every something is necessarily engaged in a process of change (Houlgate 2022, 181-2).
This in stark contrast to Kant, who maintains in the Critique of Pure Reason that all change in the sphere of appearances presupposes time (i.e. something that lasts).
Alteration can therefore be perceived only in substances, and arising or perishing per se cannot be a possible perception unless it concerns merely a determination of that which persists, for it is this very thing that persists that makes possible the representation of the transition from one state into another, and from non-being into being, which can therefore be empirically cognized only as changing determinations of that which lasts. If you assume that something simply began to be, then you would have to have a point of time in which it did not exist. But what would you attach this to, if not to that which already exists? (Kant 1998, 303/A188).
As Houlgate points out, Hegel’s conception of change here does not presuppose
time or an alteration in time. Change can be conceptualized as a process of
becoming-other
that does require time. This is not to say that change in more
concrete things in experience do require change, but the Logic here does not
endeavor to provide an account of temporal, worldly change, but conceptualizing
change as such. Hegel’s aim, as Houlgate writes, “is rather to show that, even
in the absence of time, every something must change, purely by virtue of being
other. Time is thus not the ultimate source of change; the latter is made
necessary by the simple fact that there is something and something else at all”
(Houlgate 2022, 182).
This connection between “other” and “change” is normally obscured in English, but the Latin-based word “alteration”, which contains the Latin “alter” (“other”), makes it more evident. A similar case obtains for speakers of German: Veränderung, which itself containers the word “other”—Anderes—and literally means “to-other-ize”. Yet another similar case also obtains for Norwegian speakers with the word forandre, even more than the German since “other” here is more obvious and recognizable. While these connections in language are helpful, Hegel does not derive the connection of “other” and “change” from words; the connection is a logical one, Houlgate emphasizes, in the fact that the other, when considered by itself and made explicit, “must be and constantly become the other of itself” (Houlgate 2022, 182).
The idea of change is not complete, however, without the element of identity in
the process of becoming-other
. Becoming-other
signals that an other
is not
primarily “other” vis-à-vis a something
, but it is equally other
with
regards to itself, such that is continuously different from itself. This
emphasizes the element of difference, but there is also that of identity.
Precisely as the other
becomes other to itself, it is no less, once again,
other
. Change does occur, indeed, the more it occurs the more the other
remains true to itself. “In the process of change the other thus remains the
other that it is; and the more it changes and becomes other than itself, the
more it remains the other and so remains itself” (Houlgate 2022, 182).
Paradoxically, the more the other
becomes what it is not, the more it remains
what it is. In terms of the process of change, then, the more alterations, the
more constancy is established.
As Houlgate points out, Hegel shows here that self-identity and change are not
in principle at odds with one another, as might be assumed. In fact,
self-identity is not only preserved by the process of change, but arises
through it: “that in becoming other than itself, the other does not become
something radically new, but becomes another instance of what it already is,
what it is before the change – another instance of being other”
(Houlgate 2022, 183). That it arises becomes evident in the moment of identity
in the process of becoming-other
.
Importantly, this moment of identity is not repeating what was already there but
establishes the other
to be what it is.
…in going over to this other, it only unites with itself (Hegel 2010, 92/21.108).
Houlgate carefully re-renders this passage from the German as:
goes [...] together only with itself
geht [...] nur mit sich zusammen
While this may seem to repeat what is already known at this point, Houlgate
claims that it carries the argument forward. “The point to note is that the
other does not, and cannot, ‘go together with itself’ before it changes; it
does so only through changing into that which is still (in one respect)
itself” (Houlgate 2022, 183). Exactly this “going together with itself”
effectively designates a self-relating being or something
, leading the
logical development back to something
from other
. Finally, movement implies
that becoming-other
into merely other
is not the complete process of change,
for there is also becoming-other
into a new something
.
change does not just leave us with the same old other: it does not just produce another instance of what is there already. Change also gives rise to a new something that does not, and cannot, precede the change but that arises through it (Houlgate 2022, 183).
It may appear as if the logical development hits a deadlock of ambiguity here.
When is something distinctly something versus when is it an other? How is other,
in othering, both the same old other and something new? Something
and
other
, through change, develop into more granular determinations of
being-in-itself
and being-for-other
that aim to dispel exactly these ambiguities.
If Hegel is right, then change can be adequately conceptualized without presupposing time. All that is required is the ideas of something and other, and looking carefully at the logical implications that their relationship forms.
Bibliography
- Houlgate, S. 2022. Hegel on Being. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
- Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Paul Guyer, and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Authors
Filip Niklas (2025)